
Virtue Ethics - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
2003年7月18日 · Virtue ethics is currently one of three major approaches in normative ethics. It may, initially, be identified as the one that emphasizes the virtues, or moral character, in contrast to the approach that emphasizes duties or rules (deontology) or that emphasizes the consequences of actions (consequentialism).
Virtue Ethics - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
2003年7月18日 · Three of virtue ethics' central concepts, virtue, practical wisdom and eudaimonia are often misunderstood. Once they are distinguished from related but distinct concepts peculiar to modern philosophy, various objections to virtue ethics can be better assessed.
Aristotle’s Ethics - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
2001年5月1日 · Aristotle distinguishes two kinds of virtue (1103a1–10): those that pertain to the part of the soul that engages in reasoning (virtues of mind or intellect), and those that pertain to the part of the soul that cannot itself reason but is nonetheless capable of following reason (ethical virtues, virtues of character).
Moral Character - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
2003年1月15日 · Aristotle’s view, on the other hand, is usually considered a paradigm example of a “virtue ethics”, an ethical theory that gives priority to virtuous character. To see what this might mean, recall that Aristotle’s virtuous person is a genuine self-lover who enjoys most the exercise of her abilities to think and know.
Plato’s Ethics: An Overview - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
2003年9月16日 · Like most other ancient philosophers, Plato maintains a virtue-based eudaemonistic conception of ethics. That is to say, happiness or well-being ( eudaimonia ) is the highest aim of moral thought and conduct, and the virtues ( aretê : ‘excellence’) are the dispositions/skills needed to attain it.
Justice as a Virtue - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
2002年3月8日 · Justice as a personal virtue follows Aristotle’s model for virtues of character, in which the virtue lies as an intermediate or mean between vices of excess and defect (Nicomachean Ethics V). While he grants that there is a “general” sense of justice in which justice is coincident with complete virtue, there is a “particular” sense in ...
Ancient Ethical Theory - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
2004年8月3日 · In their moral theories, the ancient philosophers depended on several important notions. These include virtue and the virtues, happiness (eudaimonia), and the soul. We can begin with virtue. Virtue is a general term that translates the Greek word aretê. Sometimes aretê is also translated as excellence.
Deontological Ethics - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
2007年11月21日 · In other words, deontology falls within the domain of moral theories that guide and assess our choices of what we ought to do (deontic theories), in contrast to those that guide and assess what kind of person we are and should be (aretaic [virtue] theories).
Virtue Epistemology - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
Virtue ethicists have long recognized a difference between self-regarding moral virtues, such as prudence and courage, and other-regarding virtues, such as benevolence and compassion. And they have recognized the importance of both sorts.
Consequentialism - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
2003年5月20日 · Another indirect version is virtue consequentialism, which holds that whether an act is morally right depends on whether it stems from or expresses a state of character that maximizes good consequences and, hence, is a virtue.